Werner Bonefeld
Introduction
Over the last decade there has been an increase in the trafficking of women and children, prostitution of slavery. New markets have emerged in human organs and babies. The proprietors of labour power are confronted not only with new forms of exploitation (see Caffentzis, 1999). They are also transformed into a saleable resource to be operated on and sold, with babies being produced for export (Federici, 1997). Some commentators have suggested that we witness the re-emergence of conditions of primitive accumulation (see, amongst others, Dalla Costa, 1995a, 1995b). These works show clearly that Marx's insight according to which 'a great deal of capital, which appears today in the United States without
certificate of birth, was yesterday, in England, the capitalist blood of
children' (Marx, 1983, p. 707), remains a powerful judgement of contemporary conditions.
This essay argues that primitive accumulation describes not just the period of
transition that led to the emergence of capitalism. Primitive accumulation is,
in fact, the foundation of the capitalist social relations and thus the social
constitution through which the exploitation of labour subsists. In other words,
contemporary developments of primitive accumulation are not 'chance'
developments. Instead, primitive accumulation is a necessary element of
capitalism. The argument, then, is that primitive accumulation is a permanently
reproduced accumulation. It is the condition and presupposition of capital's
existence. In short, primitive accumulation is a constantly reproduced
accumulation, be it in terms of the renewed separation of new populations from
the means of production and subsistence, or in terms of the reproduction of the
wage relation in the 'established' relations of capital. The former seeks to
bring new workers under the command of capital and the latter to contain them as
an exploitable human resource - the so-called human factor of production.
Capitalist social relations rest on the divorce of the mass of the population
from the means of production. This divorce was the result of primitive
accumulation and it is the presupposition on which the capitalist exploitation
of labour rests.
Primitive Accumulation and Capital
Within the Marxist tradition, primitive accumulation is usually seen as the
pre-history of capitalism. Capitalism developed out of primitive accumulation
and once capitalism had been established, the history of primitive accumulation
- a history of blood and fire where sheep replaced humans during the clearing of
estates - is seen to be just that: history. Primitive accumulation, then, is
seen as a period of historical transition from pre-capitalist to capitalist
social relations. The time specific systematic character of primitive
accumulation refers to the 'clearing of the estates', that is the separation of
labour from the means of production and the natural conditions of labour.
Marxist writing on imperialism, especially Luxemburg (1963), implicitly
acknowledged that 'capitalism proper' in the imperialist centres depends for its
own expanded reproduction on the subjugation of new populations to the
capitalist exchange relations. Luxemburg, while not denying the conventional
view that primitive accumulation is a distinct period at the dawn of capitalism,
accepted nevertheless the coincidence of constituted capitalist relations with
primitive accumulation. Importantly, however, primitive accumulation was not
seen as an 'original accumulation' but, rather, it was a consequence of the
contradictory logic of capitalism: the accumulation of capital necessitated the
opening of new markets in order to realise extracted surplus value in enchange.
In this view, then, primitive accumulation derives from the contradictory logic
of capitalist accumulation and its crisis. This made it possible for Luxemburg
to accept the view that primitive accumulation marks the period of transition to
capitalism and to argue, at least by implication, that primitive accumulation is
a feature of the crisis-ridden character of capitalist accumulation.
Amin, writing in the 1970s, focuses this issue well: the mechanisms of primitive
accumulation 'do not belong only to the prehistory of capitalism; they are
contemporary as well. It is these forms of primitive accumulation, modified but
persistent, to the advantage of the centre, that form the domain of the theory
of accumulation on a world scale' (Amin, 1974, p. 3). The understanding of
primitive accumulation as a mere period of transition fails to see that the
divorce of labour from her means of production is not just the historical
premise of capitalist social relations but, importantly, the condition and
presupposition of the capitalist exploitation of labour. As Marx (1973, p. 515)
put it, 'the exchange of labour for labour - seemingly the condition of the
workers' property - rests on the foundation of the workers' propertylessness'.
Capitalist social relations are founded on the separation of labour from the
means of production and this entails that capitalist accumulation rests on the
continuously reproduced divorce of labour from her means.
Primitive Accumulation and Social Constitution
Marx's critique of political economy made clear that 'capital' is not a 'thing'
and he argues that the standpoint of capital and wage labour is the same.
Capital is not a thing because it is a definite social relationship and the
standpoint of capital and wage labour is the same because both are perverted
forms of social reproduction. For Marx, each 'form', even the most simple form
like, for example, the commodity, 'is already an inversion and causes relations
between people to appear as attributes of things' (Marx, 1972, p. 508) or, more
emphatically, each form is a 'perverted form' (Marx, 1962, p. 90).
The most developed perversion, the constituted fetish of capitalist society, is the
relationship of capital to itself, of a thing to itself (see Marx, 1972, p.
515). The extreme expression of this perversion is interest bearing capital: the
'most externalised and most fetish-like form' of capital (Marx, 1966, p. 391).
And the 'wage' - the defining characteristic of wage labour? 'Labour - wages, or
price of labour' is an expression that 'is just as irrational as a yellow
logarithm' (ibid., p. 818). What, then, needs to be explained is not the
relation between capital and wage labour in its direct and immediate sense but
rather the social constitution upon which this relationship is founded and
through which it subsists. In other words, what needs to be explained is why
human social productice practice takes the form of capital. Hence, Marx's
question, 'why does this content [human social productive practice] assume that
form [the form of capital]' (Marx, 1962, p. 95). This question raises the issue
of the social constitution of value. The critical dimension of this insight is
this: 'it is not the unity of living and active humanity with the natural,
inorganic conditions of their metabolic exchange with nature, and hence their
appropriation of nature, which requires explanation or is the result of historic
process, but rather the separation between these inorganic conditions of human
existence and this active existence, a separation which is completely posited
only in the relation of wage labour and capital' (Marx, 1973, p. 489). The class
antagonism between capital and labour rests on and subsists through the
separation of human social practice from its means. There can be no capitalist
accumulation without the continued reproduction of labour's divorce from her
conditions.
Commodity exchange and 'money' pre-date capitalist production. For money,
however, to be 'transformed into capital, the prerequisites for capitalist
production must exist' (Marx, 1972, p. 272). The first historical presupposition
is the separation of labour from her conditions and 'therefore the existence of
the means of labour as capital' (ibid.).
For Marx, this separation comprises a world's history. 'Commodity and money are transformed into capital because the worker ... is compelled to sell his labour itself (to sell directly his labour power) as a commodity to the owner of the objective conditions of labour. This separation is the prerequisite for the relationship of capital and wage labour in the same way as it is the prerequisite for the transformation of money (or of the commodity by which it is represented) into capital' (ibid., p. 89). The constitution of human purposeful activity as relations between the thingsthemselves is based on this separation and, once established, obtains as the constitutive presupposition of capitalist social relations (see Krahl, 1971, p.223). In sum, the separation of labour from her conditions is the precondition of their existence as capital and 'is the foundation of [capitalist] production...[and] is given in capitalist production' (Marx, 1972, p. 272).
Separation means that the conditions of work confront labour 'as alien capital'
(Marx, 1972, p. 422) because the conditions of 'production are lost to [the
labourer] and have assumed the shape of alien property' (ibid.). The divorce,
then, of human purposful practice from her conditions and their transformation
into an independent force, i.e. capital, transforms the product of labour into a
commodity and makes the commodity appear as 'a product of capital' (Marx, 1966,
p. 880). This entails 'the materialisation of the social features of production
and the personification of the material foundations of production' (ibid.).
Thus, the capitalist and wage-labourer 'are as such merely embodiments,
personifications of capital and wage-labour; definite social characteristics
stamped upon individuals by the process of social production' (ibid.). In this
way, primitive accumulation appears suspended (aufgehoben) in the commodity
form. Yet, however suspended, it is the constitutive condition of capitalist
social relations as relations between things. The presuppositions of capital,
'which originally appeared as conditions of its becoming - and hence could not
spring from its action as capital - now appear as results of its own
realization, reality, as posited by it - not as conditions of its arising, but
as results of its presence' (Marx, 1973, p. 460). In short, primitive
accumulation is not just an historical epoch which pre-dates capitalist social
relations and from which capital emerged. It entails, fundamentally, the
constitutive presupposition through which the class antagonism between capital
and labour subsists - primitive accumulation is the 'foundation of capitalist
reproduction' (Marx, 1983, p. 585).
Primitive accumulation is the centrifugal point around which resolves the
specific capitalist mode of existence of labour power, the determination of
human purposeful activity in the form of a labouring commodity. While the
capitalist production and exchange relations subsist through the commodity form,
primitive accumulation is the secrete history of the determination of human
purposeful practice in the form of a wage-labouring commodity. The commodity
form subsists through this determination, presupposes it and, through its form,
denies it in the name of abstract equality and freedom.
This insight is focused in Marx's critique of fetishism: 'The sum total of the labour of all these private individuals and private groups makes up the aggregate of social labour.
Since the producers do not come into social contact which each other until they
exchange their products, the specific social character of each producer's labour
does not show itself except in the act of exchange. In other words, the labour
of the individual asserts itself as a part of the labour of society, only by
means of the relations which the act of exchange establishes directly between
the products, and indirectly, through them, between producers. To the latter,
therefore, the relations connecting the labour of one individual with that of
the rest appear, not as direct social relations between individuals at work, but
as what they really are, material relations between persons and social relations
between things' (Marx, 1983, pp. 77-8). The social individual, then, subsists as
such an individual not in an 'immediate' sense but in a 'mediated' sense: it is
mediated through the commodity form. The commodity form poses the totality of
bourgeois social relations and as such a totality posits the basis of the
productive practice of all individuals as alienated individuals. The commodity
form includes not only the activity of each individual it is, also, independent
of this connection from the individual.
The divorce, then, of labour from its conditions entails not only the complete independence of the individuals form one another but, also, their complete dependence on the seemingly impersonal relations established by the commodity form. Thus, the independence of the individual is an 'illusion, and so more accurately called indifference' (Marx, 1973, p. 162). Their independence is that of atomised market individuals that are 'free to collide with one another and to engage in exchange within this freedom' (ibid., pp. 163-64). The separation of human activity from its conditions is thus not only the real generation process of capital but, also, once constituted, the 'real' process of the commodity form. In other words, primitive accumulation is suspended in the commodity form as its 'subterranean' condition, constitutive presupposition, and historical basis.
The 'logic of separation' (cf. Negri, 1984) entails that the individual
capitalist has constantly to expand 'his capital, in order to preserve it, but
extend it he cannot, except by means of progressive accumulation' (Marx, 1983,
p. 555). The risk is bankruptcy. Thus, mediated through competition, personified
capital is spurred into action. 'Fanatically bent on making value expand itself,
[the personified capitalist] ruthlessly forces the human race to produce for
production's sake', increasing 'the mass of human beings exploited by him'
(ibid.).
The positing of the results of human labour as a force over and above
the social individual, including both the capitalist and the wage labourer, and
the 'fanatic' bent to make workers work for the sake of work, is founded on the
separation of labour from its means. 'The means of production become capital
only in so far as they have become separated from labourer and confront labour
as an independent power' (Marx, 1963, p. 408). In short, the freedom of labour
from her conditions and their transformation into private property entails the
capitalist property right to preserve abstract wealth through the 'sacrifice of
"human machines" on the pyramids of accumulation' (Gambino, 1996, p. 55). The
law of private property entails that 'labour capacity has appropriated for
itself only the subjective conditions of necessary labour - the means of
subsistence for actively producing labour capacity, i.e. for its reproduction as
mere labour capacity separated from the conditions of its realization - and it
has posited these conditions themselves as things, values, which confront it in
an alien, commanding personification' (Marx, 1973, pp. 452-53). The logic of
separation is the 'real process of capital' (Marx, 1972, p. 422). Indeed, as
Marx argues, capital is 'the separation of the conditions of production from the
labourer' (ibid.).
In sum, Marx does not conceive of capital as a thing in-itself which, endowed
with its own objective logic, exchanges itself with itself and that, by doing
so, generates profit. Rather, it is conceived as a social relationship between
labour and the conditions of labour which are 'rendered independent in relation'
to labour (ibid. 422). 'The loss of the conditions of labour by the workers is
expressed in the fact that these conditions of labour become independent as
capital or as things at the disposal of the capitalist' (ibid. p. 271).
Primitive accumulation, then, is not just a 'period' from which capitalist
social relations emerged. Rather, it is the historical 'act' that constitutes
the capitalist social relations as a whole. As Marx put it, this separation
'forms [bildet] the conception [Begriff] of capital' (Marx, 1966, p. 246). The
separation of labour from its conditions and the concentration of these in the
hands of 'non-workers' (Marx, 1978, p. 116) posits capital as a perverted form
of human social practice where the 'process of production has mastery over man,
instead of being controlled by him' (Marx, 1983, p. 85). The class struggle,
then, that freed master from serf and serf from master is constitutive of the
relation between capital and labour. Primitive accumulation, then, persists,
within the capital relation, as its constitutive pre-positing action. This
'action' lies at the heart of capital's reproduction: the pre-positing action of
the separation of labour from her means is not the historical result of capital
but its presupposition, a presupposition which renders capital a social
production relation in and through the divorce of labour's social productive
force from her conditions.
The systematic character of primitive accumulation subsists, then, in suspended
form through the constituted relations of capital. The separation is not the
result of capital but its genesis and it is now posited as the presupposition of
capital. It no longer 'figures' as the condition of its historical emergence
but, rather, as the constitutive presupposition of its fanatic bent on
reproducing human relations as relations between commodity owners and that is as social categories of capitalist reproduction. In short, the separation 'begins
with primitive accumulation, appears as a permanent process in the accumulation
and concentration of capital, and expresses itself finally as centralisation of
existing capitals in a few hands and a deprivation of many of their capital (to
which expropriation is now changed)' (Marx, 1966, p. 246).
The terror of separation, of capitalism's original beginning, weights like a
nightmare on the social practice of human purposeful activity. The
commodification of labour as wage labour means that human social practice
confronts its conditions as alien conditions, as conditions of exploitation, and
as conditions which appear, and so exist contradictorily, as relations between
things. 'Man is confronted by things, labour is confronted by its own
materialised conditions as alien, independent, self-contained subjects,
personifications, in short, as someone else's property and, in this form, as
"employers" and "commanders" of labour itself, which they appropriate instead of
being appropriated by it. The fact that value - whether it exists as money or as
commodities - and in the further development the conditions of labour confront
the worker as the property of other people, as independent properties, means
simply that they confront him as the property of the non-worker or, at any rate,
that, as a capitalist, he confronts them [the conditions of labour] not as a
worker but as the owner of value, etc., as the subject in which these things
possess their own will, belong to themselves and are personified as independent
forces' (Marx, 1972, pp. 475-76). Capital presupposes labour as wage labour and
wage labour presupposes capital as capital. Each is the precondition of the
other.
'Every pre-condition of the social reproduction process is at the same
time its result, and every one of its results appears simultaneously as its
pre-condition. All the production relations within which the process moves are
therefore just as much its products as they are its conditions. The more one
examines its nature as it really is, [the more one sees] that in the last form
it becomes increasingly consolidated, so that independently of the process these
conditions appear to determine it, and their own relations appear to those
competing in the process as objective conditions, objective forces, aspects of
things, the more so as in the capitalist process, every element, even the
simplest, the commodity for example, is already an inversion and causes
relations between people to appear as attributes of things and as relations of
people to the social attributes of things' (Marx, 1972, pp. 507-8).
The perverted form of value presents, in other words, the mode of existence of human purposeful activity the form of impersonal relations, conferring on the human being the indignity of an existence [Dasein] as a personification of things.
Thus, concerning the capital-labour relation, 'the workers produces himself as
labour capacity, as well as the capital confronting him'. At the same time, 'the
capitalist reproduces himself as capital as well as the living labour capacity
confronting him' (Marx, 1973, p. 458). 'Each reproduces itself, by reproducing
the other, its negation. The capitalist produces labour as alien; labour
produces the product as alien' (ibid.).
Once the logic of separation is taken for granted, i.e. once its constitutive
presupposition is merely assumed as a historical past, the logic of separation
can be understood merely in terms of the constituted fetish of capital as the
subject that structures the actions of human agents. Orthodox accounts feed on
this seperation between (capitalist) structure and (human) agency. As
Horkheimer (1985, p. 246) put it, the separation of 'genesis' from 'existence'
constitutes the blind spots of dogmatic thought. This does, however, not mean
that orthodox approaches can not provide an analysis of value. But they can do
so only in terms of labour as a human agency, and in terms of value as embodied
labour. This theory of value merely shows that 'the development of social labour
produces either a process of accumulation of value or a complex norm of
distribution' (Negri, 1992, p. 70). In this view, the perverted existence of
human relations as relations between things is assumed to be true in practice
and the driving force of capitalist development becomes to be seen as capital
itself. Such analytical offerings merely confirm that 'myth' is not a condition
merely of former times but, rather, that it continuous to exercise its
domination over thought itself. Hence Marx's insistence on demystification:
Neither 'nations' nor 'history' nor capital have made war. 'History does
nothing, does not "possess vast wealth", does not "fight battles"! It is Man,
rather, the real, living Man who does all that, who does possess and fight, it
is not "history" that uses Man as a means to pursue its ends, as if it were a
person apart. History is nothing but the activity of Man pursuing its ends'
(Marx/Engels, 1980, p. 98). Marx's critique of fetishism is fundamentally a
critique of unreflected presuppositions: it shows the necessity of capitalist
forms in the light of their social constitution. In short, and as Marcuse
reports, 'the constitution of the world occurs behind the backs of the
individuals, yet it is their work' (1988, p. 151).
Without an understanding of the social constitution of the perverted world of
capital, there could be no critique of capital without, at the same time,
espousing it as as performing a useful economic function. This, then, would lead
to the view of capital as 'the subject' that embodies the logic of an abstract
market structure whose empirical reality is mediated by class struggle and other
social forces (Jessop, 1991).
Against this theoretical rationalisation of capital as an extra-human force, it is only on the basis of an understanding of the logic of separation that a critique of capital can be supplied: this critique breaks into the understanding of capitalist exploitation and accumulation as a constituted form and 'unhinges this constitution and marks the singularity and the dynamics of the antagonism which the law of labour
comprehends' (Negri, 1992, p. 70). The capital relation is the historical
product of labour's alienation from itself: Capital is 'the form assumed by the
conditions of labour' (Marx, 1972, p. 492) and capital's existence rests not
just on the exploitation of labour but, rather, on the continuous accumulation
of capital through the progressive exploitation of labour (see Marx, 1983, p.
555). Labour's 'natural power' to maintain value and to create new value (cf.
ibid., p. 568) is commanded by capital in the production process which is, at
the same time, the consumption process of living labour. It is the labourer who
'constantly produces material, objective wealth, but in the form of capital, of
an alien power that dominates and exploits [the labourer]: and the capitalist as
constantly produces labour-power, but in the form of a subjective source of
wealth, separated from the objects in and by which it can alone be realised; in
short he process the labourer, but as a wage-labourer. This incessant
reproduction, this perpetuation of the labourer, is the sine qua non of
capitalist production' (ibid., pp. 535-36). Thus, the contention that capitalist
accumulation is not just based on the results of primitive accumulation but,
instead, that primitive accumulation is the constitutive presupposition of the
class antagonism between capital and labour. As Marx put it, capitalist
'accumulation merely presents as a continuous process what in primitive
accumulation, appears as a distinct historical process, as the process of the
emergence of capital' (Marx, 1972 p. 272; see also Marx, 1983, p. 688). There
would be no capitalist accumulation without the reproduction of labour as
'object-less free labour' (Marx, 1973, p. 507). The social constitution of
capitalist property rights is the divorce of labour from her means, object-less
labour 'under the command of capital' (ibid., p. 508).
The presupposition of capitalist social reproduction is the freedom of labour
from her condition; this presupposition informs and in-forms the real movement
of capitalist social relations. Capital, 'fanatically bent on making value
expand itself' (ibid., p. 555) can do no other than to intensify the division of
labour so as to increase its productive power. There is no doubt that 'the
subdivision of labour is the assassination of a people' (Urquhart, quoted in
Marx, 1983, p. 343); yet it merely consolidates the 'original' separation of
labour from its conditions through further and further fragmentations of the
social labour process, dismembering Man [Mensch] (cf. Marx, 1977, p. 155).
Still, however much social labour is fragmented, divided and subdivided, human
cooperation remains 'the fundamental form of the capitalist mode of production'
(Marx, 1983, p. 317). This cooperation exists against itself in the
commodity-form that integrates the 'assassination of a people' with the
respectful forms of equal and free exchange relations.
Labour 'is and remains the presupposition' of capital (Marx, 1973, p. 399).
Capital cannot liberate itself from labour; it depends on the imposition of
necessary labour, the constituent side of surplus labour, upon the world's
working classes. It has to posit necessary labour at the same time as which it
has to reduce necessary labour to the utmost in order to increase surplus value.
This reduction develops labour's productive power and, at the same time, the
real possibility of the realm of freedom.
The circumstance that less and less socially necessary labour time is required to produce, for want of a better expression, the necessities of life, limits the realm of necessity and so allows the blossoming of what Marx characterised as the realm of freedom. Within capitalist society, this contradiction can be contained only through force (Gewalt), including not only the destruction of productive capacities,
unemployment, worsening conditions, and widespread poverty, but also the
destruction of human life through war, ecological disaster, famine, the burning
of land, poisoning of water, devastation of communities, the production of
babies for profit, the usage of the human body as a commodity to be exchange or
operated on, the industrialisation of human production through cloning etc.
The existence of Man as a degraded, exploited, debased, forsaken and enslaved being, indicates that capitalist production is not production for humans - it is
production through humans. In other words, the value form represents not just an
abstraction from the real social individual. It is an abstraction that is 'true
in practice' (cf. Marx, 1973, p. 105). The universal reduction of all specific
human social practice to the one, some abstract form of labour, from the
battlefield to the cloning laboratory, indicates that the separation which began
with primitive accumulation appears now in the biotechnical determination to
expropriate human beings. Capitalism has gone a long way. Indifferent to life,
it 'was satisfied with nothing more than appropriating an excessive number of
working hours' (Dalla Costa, 1995a, p. 21). It is now engaged in the production
of human-workers.
Conclusion
The essay has argued that primitive accumulation is a constantly reproduced
accumulation, be it in terms of the renewed separation of new populations from
the means of production and subsistence, or in terms of the reproduction of the
wage relation in the 'established' relations of capital. The former seeks to
bring new workers under the command of capital (Dalla Costa, 1995a,b;
Caffentzis, 1995) and the latter to contain them there as social categories
'freed' from their conditions.
The struggle for human autonomy and self-determination involves the
transformation of the means of production into means of emancipation. 'The
society of the free and equal' (cf. Agnoli, 2000) or the 'mode of production of
associated producers' (cf. Godelier, 2000), can not be achieved through a
politics on behalf of the working class. As Marx (1983, p. 447) put it, 'to be
a productive labourer is...not a piece of luck, but a misfortune'. Theory on
behalf of the working class leads to the acceptance of programs and tickets
whose common basis is the everyday religion of bourgeois society: commodity
fetishism. The emancipation of the working class can only be achieved by the
working class itself; and this means the end of the working class as a social
class. Emancipation means human emancipation. Communism entails the end of
class, a classless society. The emancipation of the working class then means
that Man 'recognises and organises his "forces propres" as social forces and
thus no longer separates social forces from himself in the form of political
forces' and material forces (Marx, 1964, p. 370). Marx saw this new form of
society anticipated in the 'community of revolutionary proletarians, who extend
their own control over the conditions of their own existence and those of all
members of society. It is as individuals that the individuals participate in it.
It is exactly this combination of individuals (assuming the advanced stage of
modern productive forces, of course) which puts the conditions of the free
development and movement of individuals under their control - conditions which
were previously abandoned to chance and had won an independent existence over
and against the separate individuals precisely because of their separation as
individuals' (Marx and Engels, 1962, p. 74). In short, for humans to enter into
relationship with one another, not as separated individuals whose social
existence is made manifest behind their backs through the commodity form, but as
social individuals, as human dignities who are in control of their social
conditions, the economic 'mastery of capital over man' has to be abolished so
that man's social reproduction is 'controlled by him' (cf. Marx, 1983, p. 85).
Paraphrasing Adorno (1975, p. 44), full-employment makes sense in a society
where labour is no longer the measure of all things. In other words, then, the
labour theory of value presupposes the separation of human social practice from
its conditions. It is this presupposition that constitutes the capitalist
exploitation of labour and it is this presupposition that the struggle for human
emancipation has to put into the museum of antiquities. Human cooperation has to
be liberated from its antagonistic link to capital. Within capitalism,
cooperation is a contradictory productive force. 'Not only have we here an
increase in the productive power of the individual, by means of cooperation, but
the creation of a new power, namely, the collective power of the masses' (Marx,
1983, p. 309). It is of course the case that the critique of political economy
can be made manifest in practice only when it has seized the masses; when, in
other words, the masses are seized by the understanding that it is their own
labour, their social practice, that produces a world that oppresses them (cf.
Marx, 1975, p. 182). This world is a world of separation, of 'object-less'
labour. What needs to be overcome, then, is the alienation of human social
practice from her conditions. It is this alienation that constitutes the
relationship between wage labour and capital.
Bibliography
Adorno, T. (1975), Gesellschaftstheorie und Kulturkritik, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt.
Agnoli, J. (2000), 'The Market, the State and the End of History', in Bonefeld,
W. and K. Psychopedis (eds) The Politics of Change, Plagrave, London.
Amin, S. (1974), Accumulation on a World Scale. A critique of the theory of
Underdevelopment, Monthly Review Press, New York.
Bonefeld, W. (1988), 'Class Struggle and the Permanence of Primitive
Accumulation', Common Sense no. 8.
Bonefeld, W. (1993), 'Crisis of Theory', Capital & Class, no. 50.
Bonefeld, W. (1999), ''Notes on Competition, Capitalist Crises and Class',
Historical Materialism, no. 5.
Bonefeld, W. (2001), 'Labour, Capital and Primitive Accumulation: Class and
Constitution', forthcoming in Dinerstein, A. and M. Neary (eds) The Labour
Debate, Ashgate, Aldershot.
Brenner, R. (1998), 'The Economics of Global Turbulance', New Left Review, no.
229.
Caffentzis, G. (1995), 'The Fundamental Implications of the Debt Crisis for
Social Reproduction in Africa', in Dalla Costa, M. and G.F. Dalla Costa (eds)
Paying the Price, Zed Books, London.
Caffentzis, G. (1999), 'The End of Work or the Rennzissance of Slavery?', Common
Sense, no. 24.
Dalla Costa, M. (1995a), 'Development and Reproduction', Common Sense no. 17.
Dalla Costa, M. (1995b), 'Capitalism and Reproduction', in Bonefeld, W. etal.
(eds.) Open Marxism: Emancipating Marx, Pluto, London.
de Angelis, M. (1999), '
Marx's Theory of Primitive Accumulation: a Suggested Reinterpretation'
Federici, S. (1997), 'Reproduction and Feminist Struggle in the New
International Division of Labour', in Dalla Costa, M. and G.F. Dalla Costa (eds)
Women, Development and Labour Reproduction, African World Press, Lawrenceville.
Gambino, R. (1996), 'A Critique of the Fordism and the Regulation School',
Common Sense no. 19.
Godelier, M. (2000), 'The Disappearance of the "Socialist System": Failure or
Confirmation of Marx's View on the Transition from One Form of Production and
Society to Another?', in Bonefeld, W. and K. Psychopedis (eds), The Politics of
Change, Palgrave, London.
Holloway, J. (1995), 'Capital Moves', Capital & Class no. 57.
Horkheimer, M. (1985), Zur Kritik der instrumentellen Vernunft, Fischer,
Frankfurt.
Jessop, B. (1991), 'Polar Bears and Class Struggle', in Bonefeld, W. and J.
Holloway (eds) Post-Fordism and Social Form, Macmillan, London.
Krahl, J. (1971), Konstitution und Klassenkampf, Verlag Neue Kritik, Frankfurt,
4th ed. 1985.
Lebowitz, M (1999), 'In Brenner, Everything is Reversed', Historical
Materialism, no. 4.
Luxemburg, R. (1963), The Accumulation of Capital, Routldege, London.
Marcuse, H. (1988), 'Philosophy and Critical Theory', in ibid. Negations, Free
Association Press, London.
Marx, K. (1962), Das Kapital, vol. I, MEW 23, Dietz Verlag, Berlin.
Marx, K. (1963), Theories of Surplus Value Part I, Lawrence & Wishart, London.
Marx, K. (1964), Zur Judenfrage, in MEW 1, Dietz, Berlin.
Marx, K. (1966), Capital Vol. III, Lawrence & Wishart, London.
Marx, K. (1972), Theories of Surplus Value Part III, Lawrence & Wishart, London.
Marx, K. (1973), Grundrisse, Penguin, Harmondsworth.
Marx, K. (1975), 'Contribution to Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Law.
Introduction', Collected Works, vol. 3, Lawrence & Wishart, London.
Marx, K. (1977), Das Elend der Philosophy, MEW 4, Dietz, Berlin.
Marx, K. (1978), Capital, Vol. II, Penguin, Harmondsworth.
Marx, K. (1983), Capital, vol. I, Lawrence & Wishart, London.
Marx, K. and F. Engels (1962), Die deutsche Ideology, MEW 3, Dietz, Berlin.
Marx, K. and F. Engels (1980), Die heilige Familie, MEW 2, Dietz, Berlin.
Negri, A. (1984), Marx beyond Marx, Bergin & Garvey, Massachusetts.
Negri, A. (1992), 'Interpretation of the Class Situation Today', in Bonefeld, W.
etal. (eds.) Open Marxism: Theory and Practice, Pluto, London.
Negt, O. and A. Kluge (1981), Geschiche und Eigensinn, Verlag 2001, Frankfurt.
Psychopedis, K. (1992), 'Dialectical Theory', in Bonefeld, W. etal. (eds.) Open
Marxism: Dialectics and History, Pluto, London.
Wildcat and J. Holloway (1999), 'Wildcat (Germany) reads John Holloway - A
Debate on Marxism and the Politics of Dignity', Common Sense, no. 24.
NOTE
This section draws on de Angelis (1999). De Angelis' insighful
conceptualisation of primitive accumulation as a constantly renewed accumulation
is taken up in this essay. See also Bonefeld (1988; 2001).
In the English translation the German verrckt Form, is translated as 'absurd
form' (Marx, 1983, p. 80). The translation is 'absurd'. In German, 'verrckt'
has two meanings: verrckt (mad) and ver-rckt (displaced). Thus, the notion of
'perverted forms' means that these forms are both mad and displaced. In the
following 'perversion' or 'perverted' will be used in this double sense.
I am quoting from the German edition of Capital since the English edition
omits this all important sentence.
'In fact, the realm of freedom actually begins only where labour which is
determined by necessity and mundane considerations ceases; thus in the very
nature of things it lies beyond the sphere of actual material
production...Freedom in this field can only consist in socialised Man [Mensch],
the associated producers, rationally regulating their interchange with Nature,
bringing it under their common control, instead of being ruled by the blind
forces of Nature...But it nonetheless still remains a realm of necessity. Beyond
it begins that development of human energy which is an end in itself, the true
realm of freedom, which, however, can blossom forth only with this realm of
necessity as its basis' (Marx, 1966, p. 820).
See Marx (1966, Ch. 48).
See Marx (1966, p. 880; 1972, p. 491).
On this see: Negt and Kluge (1981).
On this see Holloway (1995).
On this see Psychopedis (1992).
For a critique, see Bonefeld (1993).
See,for example, Brenner (1998) where capitalist competition is emphasised as
the constituting force of capitalist development.
For critique see, Bonefeld
(1999) and Lebowitz (1999).
See the exchange between Wildcat
and Holloway for a useful exchange on this issue (Wildcat, 1999).